This is a critique of the conversation from the video:
There exists a peculiar paradox at the heart of modern neuroscience and philosophy—one that insists that despite our ability to reflect, deliberate, and act with intent, free will is nothing more than an illusion. Figures like [SH], wrapped in the certainty of their pop-neuroscientific reductionism, argue that our thoughts and actions simply arise, devoid of conscious agency. They tell us that because we cannot predict our next thought with perfect clarity, we must be passive spectators in our own lives, carried helplessly along by random events.
But this argument is not new. It is merely the latest iteration of an age-old fatalistic doctrine, now cloaked in scientific terminology. [SH] is not the first to claim that agency is an illusion, nor will he be the last to mistake complexity for inevitability. The flaw in his reasoning, however, lays in his fundamental misunderstanding of how cognition operates—the intricate interplay between conscious deliberation, procedural learning, and reflexive response.
This sermon is not merely a critique of [SH]’s flawed perspective; it is an affirmation of something deeper—a neoBuddhist exploration of self-mastery, cognitive refinement, and the integration of conscious intent with intuitive action. Where [SH] sees passivity, we recognize cultivation. Where he insists that our actions emerge without authorship, we understand that skill, wisdom, and virtue are the result of disciplined refinement.
To accept [SH]’s worldview is to surrender to a form of intellectual nihilism—a world in which morality, responsibility, and even personal growth are illusions. But we know better. We have lived the experience of training our minds, honing our skills, and shaping our virtues with deliberate effort. And in doing so, we have proven, through direct experience, that free will is not an illusion, but a process—one that is cultivated, strengthened, and refined through conscious practice.
The following discussion will dismantle the myths of determinism, clarify the distinction between unconscious reflexes and trained expertise, and illustrate why true transcendence is not the absence of self, but its refinement into something greater. Let us begin.
Sam Harris, [SH]
Roger Penrose, [RP]
and Sophie Scott [SS]
[00:00.000] [SH] if we had a cure for psychopathy right if we had a cure for human evil
[00:04.160] if we totally understood it at the level of the brain we would just give the cure
[00:08.560] sam the last uh major topic of our discussion is whether or not we can have such a thing as
[00:21.540] moral responsibility and personal rights if we're getting rid of this idea of the self altogether
[00:27.880] so i'm interested for your views on that how it works out practically and ethically but also
[00:32.680] the same time i do want to push you on this question which uh rogers said this view that
[00:38.180] rogers has been presenting there which is why can't you say that we are simply just our conscious
[00:43.600] experiences you don't deny that consciousness exists you say it's not illusory why not say
[00:49.180] that these fleeting conscious experiences are what selves are well that's fine but that's just
[00:57.240] not how most
[00:57.860] people feel themselves to be in moment to moment right so yeah i think you are identical again as
[01:03.860] a matter from the first person side as a matter of experience they're simply experience right you're
[01:09.280] identical to experience but most people so most people feel like there's they're almost like
[01:14.340] they're on the bank of a river watching the contents of consciousness go by as though they
[01:20.340] were on the edge of the of experience you know you're either in the center of your experience
[01:25.500] you're on the edge of it but you're not identical to it whereas in reality there's there's only the
[01:31.420] river right you are the river yeah you're not you're not watching it you're you're not a you're
[01:36.280] not in a boat on top of it you're identical to it and and yet most people don't feel that most of
A Critique of [SH] on Free Will, Psychopathy, and Moral Agency
[SH]’s discussion in this transcript is a prime example of reductionist overconfidence—asserting broad claims on subjects that require deep, nuanced understanding, yet displaying little evidence of having engaged with them beyond surface-level conjecture.
The Fallacy of a "Cure for Psychopathy"
[SH] suggests that if we "totally understood" psychopathy at the level of the brain, we could simply "cure" it. This statement is both vague and misleading, as it collapses multiple, distinct issues into an ill-defined solution. Psychopathy is not a singular condition with a singular cause; it encompasses a range of behavioral and neurological traits, some of which stem from structural differences in the brain, such as reduced activity in the amygdala and prefrontal cortex. These are not conditions that can simply be "cured" with a pharmaceutical intervention or some abstract neuroscientific breakthrough.
More importantly, this assertion exposes [SH]’s lack of engagement with the actual science of psychopathy. His framing of the problem suggests he sees it as a monolithic, pathological aberration, when in reality, psychopathy exists on a spectrum, influenced by both biology and environment. His take is akin to claiming that because we understand the mechanics of vision, blindness should be curable in all cases—a naive and overly simplistic assumption that ignores the nuances of brain development, injury, and adaptability.
If anything, [SH]’s assertion implies a deterministic view that completely ignores the ethical, social, and developmental factors at play. He provides no mechanism for this "cure," no engagement with actual psychological or neuroscientific research—just a broad, reductionist assumption that complex behavioral conditions can be resolved through a singular, scientific intervention.
The River Metaphor and the Oversimplification of Consciousness
[SH]’s analogy—that most people "feel" as if they are watching their experiences from the riverbank, when in reality, they are the river—presents several fundamental issues. First, his framing assumes that people primarily perceive themselves as detached observers of their own experience. This is simply incorrect; most people do not operate in a persistent third-person perspective, watching their consciousness unfold from the outside. Rather, they are immersed in their first-person experience, a state that inherently biases perception and distorts objective self-reflection.
His analogy is an attempt to force the phrase "stream of consciousness" into a concrete metaphor, but in doing so, he conflates multiple distinct aspects of cognition:
- The internal dialogue (the verbalized thought process many experience),
- The raw, non-verbal cognitive processes that operate in the background,
- The persistent sense of self, which exists beyond momentary experiences.
By reducing consciousness to merely a sequence of fleeting experiences, [SH] ignores the continuity of identity and the underlying cognitive structures that persist over time. While momentary thoughts and emotions may be transient, the perspective from which these experiences arise is not fleeting—it maintains coherence and continuity, forming what we recognize as personal identity.
This is a classic example of reductionism gone awry: taking a concept that is rich, layered, and multifaceted, and flattening it into a one-dimensional description that fails to capture its full complexity.
Determinism and the Pitfall of Neuroessentialism
[SH]’s view leans heavily on neuroessentialism, the belief that all human behavior can be fully explained by neurological activity alone. While the brain is undoubtedly central to cognition and behavior, this perspective ignores the role of learning, adaptation, and agency in shaping who we become.
By treating free will and moral responsibility as mere illusions, [SH] implies that people are simply biological machines reacting to stimuli, with no ability to grow, change, or refine their character. This isn’t based on any rigorous neuroscience—it’s based on a pop-science misinterpretation of determinism. If behavior were solely dictated by neural activity, devoid of self-directed change, no one would ever develop new habits, overcome past traumas, or reshape their thinking through education and reflection.
Of course, someone with an elementary understanding of the brain might be overconfident in the idea that "everything is predetermined"—that’s how the Dunning-Kruger effect works. The less you know, the more confident you are in your conclusions. [SH] presents his arguments with a certainty that suggests deep understanding, but in reality, his takes are a regurgitation of reductionist determinism repackaged as wisdom.
Conclusion: The Hubris of Overconfidence
[SH]’s discussion in this transcript is an exemplar of intellectual overreach. He takes broad, complicated topics—psychopathy, free will, moral agency—and distills them into oversimplified assertions that do little to illuminate the realities of these subjects. His reliance on reductionist metaphors and determinist assumptions is not grounded in rigorous scientific inquiry but rather in a shallow, pop-neuroscience approach that lacks both depth and precision.
If one is to speak authoritatively on such subjects, it would be wise to first understand them. Unfortunately, what we have here is a demonstration of confidence outpacing competence, a hallmark of pseudo-intellectualism.
[01:43.160] the time and when you do feel that when you lose your sense of being separate from experience when
[01:48.860] you lose your sense of looking over your own shoulder in each moment from the edge of your
[01:53.080] experience that's quite a
[01:55.500] for many people it can be scary but for for you know most people it's quite a thrilling
[02:00.100] experience of self-transcendence right it's it's it's that is the basis of of virtually all of our
[02:07.640] contemplative mysticism and and you know and certainly esoteric religious aspiration right
[02:13.140] so there's a a vast literature about how good experience gets when you can when you can stop
[02:18.980] feeling like you're separate from it right so that's um but no it's yes to answer your question
[02:25.500] i think we are identical to consciousness and its contents in each moment and there's no
[02:30.540] real duality between those two things i mean there's what you're calling the contents of
[02:35.100] consciousness in each moment is an expression of consciousness it's like a you know the images in
[02:39.580] a mirror being inseparable from the the reflective quality of the mirror or your waves in an ocean
[02:45.020] being inseparable from the water it's like the waves aren't properly properly thought of as
[02:49.980] objects in the ocean they're expressions of the ocean and so again i'm not making metaphysical
[02:55.500] claims about how all of this relates to the big bang or to to physical reality i'm just talking
[03:01.920] about the the character the character of experience when you pay sufficiently close
[03:06.220] attention to it um as for moral responsibility when you lose a sense of self you notice that
** The River Metaphor and the Levels of Sapience**
[SH]’s claim that “you are the river” rather than watching it from a boat completely misunderstands the nature of cognition. If we frame this metaphor within the 7 Levels of Sapience, we see that what he describes as self-transcendence is actually Level 4 Sapience, which aligns with the cognitive capacity of dogs.
- At Level 4, an entity is immersed in its experience, reacting to stimuli but lacking full self-awareness or metacognition.
- True self-transcendence—at Level 6+ Sapience—requires the capacity for a self, because recognizing others as selves is a prerequisite for moving beyond one's own ego.
- This means that [SH] isn’t describing enlightenment at all—he’s describing regression into a more primitive state of consciousness, one that precedes the ability to step outside oneself.
By his own logic, if “being one with the river” were the highest state, then a dog or a toddler would be the pinnacle of enlightenment, as both exist in immersive experience without the reflective capacity for self-awareness. But we recognize that humans develop beyond this stage, not regress back into it to achieve wisdom.
This is where his misunderstanding becomes clear—he is mistaking a developmental phase of early cognition for a higher level of wisdom.
** The "Looking Over Your Own Shoulder" Metaphor: A Misinterpretation of Self-Reflection**
[SH] argues that people "look over their own shoulder" in life, implying they observe themselves from a detached perspective. This metaphor crudely maps video game perspectives onto human cognition, treating third-person perspective as a default.
- This perspective aligns with Level 5 Sapience, which includes theory of other minds—a prerequisite for true self-awareness.
- Most people do not exist in this perspective by default—it takes effort to analyze one’s own thoughts and actions from an external view.
[SH] gets it backwards—people don’t start as detached observers of their own experience and then “transcend” into immersion. Instead, the ability to self-reflect is an advanced cognitive feature, not a primitive illusion to be discarded.
To use his own metaphor against him, if people truly lived in constant self-observation, they wouldn’t be so prone to cognitive biases, irrational emotional reactions, or immersion in impulsive actions. The very fact that people struggle to gain self-awareness demonstrates that it is not the default state.
** Conflating Qualia with Consciousness**
[SH] makes the critical error of confusing qualia (elements of experience, like the expirience of sweetness) with consciousness itself.
He implies that because people experience the contents of consciousness, they are identical to those contents.
- This is like saying that experiencing the color red makes one "be" the color red.
- It conflates perception with identity, a mistake that ignores how conscious awareness exists independently of any single momentary experience.
This is a fundamental category error. Consciousness is not reducible to a single experience any more than a river is reducible to a ripple.
** Overconfidence in Pop-Neuroscience and Determinism**
[SH]’s deterministic view of selfhood is deeply flawed because it treats the self as an illusion while simultaneously relying on it to argue for a deterministic model of behavior.
- He ignores the capacity for neuroplasticity, adaptation, and cognitive self-modification.
- His stance ultimately implies that humans are no different from deterministic creatures, shaped entirely by external conditions—which completely contradicts the very existence of intellectual development, self-discipline, and personal growth.
This is an example of overconfidence in pop-neuroscience—the tendency to take reductionist explanations of the brain and overextend them into grand philosophical claims without scientific backing.
His arguments are ultimately self-defeating. If there is no true self, who is it that makes decisions, reflects, changes, and acts with intention? If we were truly only the river, we wouldn’t be able to recognize the river, let alone reflect on it.
** The Mistake of Assuming All Mysticism is the Same**
[SH] claims that all contemplative mysticism points to "how good experience gets when you stop feeling separate from it."
This is factually incorrect and deeply egocentric:
- Not all mystical traditions advocate for self-dissolution as the path to enlightenment. Some focus on discipline, mastery over desire, and self-restraint.
- His stance is a form of egocentrism disguised as enlightenment, assuming that because he found meaning in self-dissolution, that must be universal.
- It’s the same reasoning as claiming that “all dogs are happy because of genetics,” rather than acknowledging that happiness varies by environment, experience, and temperament.
Even more critically, his claim undermines the value of self-control by portraying distance from experience as inherently bad. If true, this would mean delayed gratification, emotional regulation, and rational thinking are all impediments to enlightenment—when in reality, these are precisely the cognitive skills that allow for higher-order wisdom.
Conclusion: Why [SH]’s View is a Misinterpretation, Not a Revelation
[SH] mistakes disruption of neurochemistry for spiritual enlightenment, misunderstands self-reflection as an illusion, and confuses qualia with consciousness.
- His metaphors collapse under scrutiny, as they misrepresent cognitive science and human development.
- His deterministic worldview ignores the complexities of selfhood, neuroplasticity, and personal agency.
- His pop-neuroscience approach breeds overconfidence, leading him to present simplistic metaphysical claims as absolute truths using clunky metaphors. Even the spiritual elephant would have been a more accurate metaphor here.
Rather than being a profound insight, [SH]’s claim is a repackaging of an earlier stage of cognition result from the disruption of neurological circuits via psychedelics as if it were enlightenment. True enlightenment requires recognizing the self, not dissolving it into experience.
[03:14.500] you that thoughts and and even the most deliberate acts of willing simply arise on their own right i
[03:21.400] mean no there's no one in that room there who knows what they're going to think next
[03:25.500] until the thought itself arises right i mean you can just perform this experiment on yourself just
[03:31.280] you say everybody think of a film you know it just just wait there's hundreds if not thousands
[03:37.560] of movies you know the titles of think of one now whatever you thought of it is an absolute
[03:44.800] mystery as to why you thought of that i mean even if you have a story about why you thought of it
[03:49.640] the truth is there were there were dozens there were hundreds of films you could have thought of
[03:54.320] but you didn't
[03:55.500] and and to and to say you could have thought of them is it's a kind of illusion in that
[04:03.620] if we re rewound your experience you know to the to to if we returned your brain to the state it
[04:09.980] was in a moment ago you would have produced exactly the same the film memory as you did
[04:16.540] you do that a trillion times in a row and if you add randomness to this picture it still doesn't
[04:20.740] give you the free will people think they have because you know that's just you know
[04:25.480] randomness is not what what people imagine they have when they they really believe they have agency
[04:31.160] so so i think when you when you look at people's behavior even you know morally important behavior
[04:36.680] like you know committing murders you have to you have to see that everyone on some level
[04:43.080] is a force of nature right they didn't make themselves they didn't make their genes they
[04:46.920] didn't make the environment to which their genes were were um by which their genes were influenced
[04:55.480] and and the combination of genes and environment are precisely what created the states of their
[04:59.600] brain prior to their last action um but this this doesn't mean that everyone gets off by
[05:05.460] reason of insanity i mean the the fact is we still need to lock people away in prison
[05:10.380] yeah when they're too dangerous to let out of prison right but the the crucial point morally
Misunderstanding Mirrors and the Nature of Consciousness
[SH] claims that "images in a mirror are inseparable from the reflective surface", using this as an analogy for how consciousness arises from the brain. This metaphor fails at a basic level of physics:
- The image in a mirror is not part of the mirror. The image exists only because light bounces off the surface, travels through the air, and is interpreted by the observer’s brain.
- By contrast, waves in the ocean are materially part of the ocean—they are not merely reflections but physical manifestations of kinetic energy in a fluid medium.
- A mirror does not “contain” the images it reflects, just as the brain does not merely “contain” consciousness in a passive way.
This reveals a fundamental misunderstanding of both consciousness and physics—ironically, from someone who often presents himself as a champion of scientific literacy. He conflates reflection with embodiment, perception with reality.
If [SH]'s claim were correct, a mirror would “own” the images it reflects—yet the moment the object moves, the image disappears. Similarly, consciousness is not a passive surface that merely reflects experience; it is an active, self-modifying process.
This is the first fundamental failure of his metaphor, but it’s not the last.
The Self-Refuting "Think of a Movie" Thought Experiment
[SH] asks his audience to "think of a movie title", using the unpredictable nature of their response to claim that free will is an illusion. This argument is self-refuting in multiple ways:
- [SH] had already planned what people were going to do before they did it. The very fact that he anticipated their thoughts, structured the setup, and expected an outcome contradicts his claim that thoughts arise purely at random.
- If his premise were true, then even he wouldn’t have been able to predict the structure of their response. But he clearly expected them to think of a movie title, which means he was engaging in intentional, directed cognition—the very thing he denies exists.
Furthermore:
- Thinking of a movie spontaneously ≠ all thought is spontaneous.
- Goal-directed cognition exists. If you were told, “Think of a movie that came out between 1990 and 2000 that features a strong female protagonist”, you could filter options based on memory and criteria—something that requires deliberate cognition.
- The monkey mind (spontaneous thought generation) does wander aimlessly at times, but that does not mean all thought arises this way.
[SH] ignores planning, self-directed thought, and the ability to structure cognition toward a goal. The very fact that he structured his own argument contradicts his conclusion.
The Contradiction Between Determinism and Randomness
[SH] argues:
- The brain is deterministic (it will always make the same decision if rewound).
- Adding randomness does not give you free will either.
These two claims contradict each other:
- If the brain is deterministic, it should always produce the same results under identical conditions.
- If randomness is involved, then the system is not deterministic.
He attempts to deny both determinism and randomness while arguing for both—a contradiction so glaring it’s astonishing it went unchallenged.
Furthermore, free will is not defined as randomness—but that’s the false dichotomy he presents.
- Randomness is not free will, but neither is determinism.
- Free will is the ability to structure cognition, plan, and make directed choices based on experience and reasoning.
By rejecting both determinism and randomness as flawed models, he accidentally points toward something beyond those constraints—free will—but refuses to acknowledge it.
The "Force of Nature" Argument is Defeatist and Ignores Human Development
[SH] claims that humans are just the product of genes and environment, ignoring:
- Self-development and self-actualization.
- The ability to shape one’s environment over time.
- The fact that adults can choose their environment.
His view only applies to children, who indeed do not choose their genes or initial environment. But once an individual reaches maturity:
- They can change who they associate with.
- They can modify their own behavior through deliberate effort.
- They can engage in mindfulness, self-discipline, and personal growth.
The reality of neuroplasticity and self-directed change outright refutes his claim. If people were purely deterministic forces of nature, no one would ever improve themselves, acquire new skills, or change their behavior in meaningful ways.
The Self-Defeating Nature of His Criminal Justice View
[SH] concedes that we still need to imprison people, despite claiming that:
- No one chooses their actions.
- Free will does not exist.
- People are merely deterministic outputs of genes and environment.
If that were true, then:
- Punishment would be meaningless, as people had no choice in their actions.
- Moral responsibility would not exist.
- Criminal rehabilitation would be impossible, since self-change is impossible.
Yet, he still supports locking people up.
- Why? Because even he cannot accept the logical conclusion of his own argument.
- If he were consistent, he would have to argue that prison is arbitrary punishment for people who were "destined" to commit crimes.
- But since he accepts that criminals should be removed from society, he implicitly acknowledges moral responsibility—which contradicts everything else he’s said.
This is a prime example of intellectual inconsistency.
[SH]’s Worldview is a Regression to Childhood, Not Transcendence
When we step back, what is the pattern in all of [SH]’s assertions?
- His view of consciousness is that of an infant—immersed in experience, lacking metacognition.
- His view of thought is that of a child’s pre-symbolic cognition—random, unstructured, purely reactive.
- His view of morality is deterministic and passive—there is no real responsibility, only forces of nature at work.
Ironically, this is the opposite of transcendence.
- True transcendence is not dissolving into experience.
- True transcendence is rising above the immediacy of experience, gaining insight, wisdom, and self-control.
[SH]’s worldview is not a higher state of being—it is a regression to early childhood cognition, where everything is reactive, deterministic, and unstructured.
This undermines everything he believes he is arguing for.
Conclusion: [SH]’s Self-Defeating Determinism
[SH] presents himself as an intellectual leader but fails to recognize the blatant contradictions in his own argument.
- He misunderstands physics (mirrors do not “contain” images).
- He misrepresents cognition (mistaking spontaneous thought for all thought).
- He contradicts himself (claiming the brain is both deterministic and random).
- He denies self-actualization (ignoring the capacity for self-directed change).
- He is inconsistent on moral responsibility (denying free will but supporting criminal punishment).
- His worldview is not enlightenment—it is regression to childhood.
In short, his philosophy collapses under its own contradictions.
[05:15.340] is that if we had a cure for psychopathy right if we had a cure for human evil if we totally
[05:21.720] understood it at the level of the brain we would just give the cure right in the end we would give
[05:25.480] And we wouldn't think it would make any moral sense to withhold the cure from psychopaths because they really deserve to be in prison and to remain psychopaths.
[05:34.540] We would recognize that psychopathy is on some basic level a derangement of the brain, and we would cure that in the same way we would cure diabetes or anything else we would
want to cure for people.
[05:46.400] And it's the fact that the actual causes of the worst forms of immoral behavior are still mysterious to us that we attribute them to the agent and imagine that the agent shou
ld have complete control over who he or she is when we know that no one made themselves, right?
[06:09.520] And no one brought their brain to the precise moment it was in a moment ago.
The False Equivalence: "Psychopathy is Like Diabetes"
[SH] incorrectly presents psychopathy as a binary medical condition, ignoring that it is:
- A spectrum rather than a singular disease.
- A complex interplay of neurophysiology, cognition, and behavior.
- Not purely genetic—environmental and social factors shape its manifestation.
By comparing psychopathy to diabetes, [SH]:
- Implies it is a singular, static condition—when in reality, psychopathy varies in severity and expression.
- Ignores that genetics alone do not determine psychopathy—many individuals carry the genetic and neurological correlates of psychopathy without exhibiting antisocial behavior.
- Fails to acknowledge the difference between primary psychopathy and antisocial behavior disorders, which share behavioral similarities but not necessarily genetic origins.
This false equivalence flattens a complex psychological condition into a simplistic medical analogy, leading to false conclusions about moral behavior.
[SH]’s Logical Leap: "Psychopathy is the Basis for All Immoral Behavior"
[SH] makes the absurd claim that psychopathy is at the root of all immoral behavior, which:
- Directly contradicts historical and cultural evidence of moral evolution.
- Ignores that morality itself is not biologically fixed but socially constructed.
- Overlooks the fact that non-psychopaths commit immoral acts regularly.
This logic mirrors the now-debunked "Super Predator" theory, which claimed that certain people—often young Black men—were biologically predisposed to violence and criminality.
- This racist and discredited theory led to draconian sentencing laws, mass incarceration, and unjust policies.
- [SH]’s argument follows a similar path, treating "immorality" as something biologically hardwired rather than shaped by cultural, social, and economic factors.
By his logic, all humans are psychopaths, since all humans have committed immoral acts at some point—even as children. This is both absurd and completely at odds with scientific understanding.
The Case of Dr. James H. Fallon: The Social Component of Psychopathy
One of the strongest counterexamples to [SH]’s argument is the case of Dr. James H. Fallon, a neuroscientist who:
- Has the genetic and neurological markers of psychopathy.
- Exhibits some psychopathic traits but is not criminal or antisocial.
- Describes himself as a "pro-social psychopath" who channels his traits productively.
This single case dismantles [SH]’s argument in multiple ways:
- It proves that psychopathy is not purely genetic—as social environment influences behavior.
- It highlights the distinction between neurological predisposition and behavioral manifestation.
- It shows that psychopathy itself does not automatically lead to immoral or criminal behavior.
If [SH]’s deterministic view were correct, Fallon should have been a violent offender, not a scientist studying his own brain.
Fallon’s case is not unique—many high-functioning individuals exhibit psychopathic traits without engaging in antisocial behavior.
This means:
- Psychopathy is not a "disease" in the traditional sense.
- Moral and antisocial behavior are shaped by socialization, personal choice, and environmental reinforcement.
- If [SH] truly cared about reducing "immorality," he would focus on rehabilitating antisocial behavior rather than obsessing over genetics.
The Real Issue: Antisocial Behavior Disorders
If [SH] was serious about "curing psychopathy," he would focus on:
- Antisocial Behavior Disorders (ASPD), which manifest in psychopathic behaviors but do not always stem from psychopathy itself.
- The environmental, cognitive, and social reinforcements that shape antisocial behaviors.
- The fact that many people who engage in immoral actions are not psychopaths.
Psychopathy and ASPD are distinct but overlapping categories:
- Primary psychopathy is associated with genetic and neurological factors.
- ASPD is more often linked to childhood trauma, abuse, neglect, or social reinforcement of immoral behavior.
[SH] ignores this entirely, because his view is too reductionist to account for the complexities of personality, behavior, and moral decision-making.
The Role of Epigenetics: How Psychopathy Can Develop Over Time
[SH] treats psychopathy as something binary—you either have it or you don’t.
This is scientifically incorrect because:
- Psychopathy can be intensified through poor lifestyle choices and epigenetic factors.
- Neurophysiological changes can increase antisocial tendencies over time.
- Trauma, stress, and environment can contribute to psychopathic-like traits.
This means:
- Someone born with normal genetics can develop psychopathic behaviors.
- Someone born with psychopathic genetics can live a pro-social life.
This undermines [SH]’s entire argument, because:
- Psychopathy is not purely genetic.
- Antisocial behavior is not purely neurological.
- Moral behavior is not static or biologically predetermined.
In some cases, psychopathy-like behaviors can be "cured" or mitigated, but [SH] is too obsessed with genetic determinism to acknowledge this.
The “Logic” that [SH] uses is the same logic that was used for the now debunked Super predator myths. Which I might add, are racist. The biggest problem with this line if reasoning, is that it is possible to have the genetic predisposition for psychopathy, without having psychopathic behaviors. Most noteably Dr. James H. Fallon and who stated that he had the neurological and genetic correlates of psychopathy, categorized himself as a "pro-social psychopath".
This is mostly important because it brings to attention the social and psychological aspects. There are many people who do not have the neurological and genetic correlates of psychopathy, while still having the same behaviors and psychology. This is called anti-social behavior disorder. Now interestingly, while those typically result in what we would call immoral behavior, it is not the basis of moral or immoral behaviors. Morality changes over time, many things which used to be considered moral, are considered immoral today. So it's preposterous to try to claim the basis for such a change, is some kind of genetic mutation.
[SH]’s flawed understanding of psychopathy and moral responsibility sets the stage for a more important discussion on the actual neurological impacts of modern behavior—specifically, the physiological changes in the brain associated with compulsive internet and social media use.
While [SH] obsesses over genetics and determinism, he completely ignores the more immediate and observable effects of environmental stimuli on brain structure—a topic far more relevant to understanding shifts in human behavior than his outdated pop-neuroscience takes on psychopathy.
The Reality of "Brain Rot": A Physiological Perspective
While [SH] dismisses the idea of agency and cognitive change, modern neuroscience has demonstrated that repetitive internet and social media use physically alters the brain in ways that affect moral reasoning, impulse control, and decision-making.
In medical literature, this phenomenon is referred to as Problematic Use of the Internet (PUI)—but the term "Brain Rot" more accurately captures the degenerative cognitive effects of compulsive screen engagement, particularly with social media.
A few major meta-analyses shed light on these changes:
- Structural Gray Matter Differences in Problematic Usage of the Internet
- Neuropsychological Deficits in Disordered Screen Use Behaviors
- Executive functions and their disorders Imaging in clinical neuroscience
The studies demonstrate significant changes in key brain regions, particularly those responsible for:
- Inhibitory control (the ability to resist impulsive behavior)
- Decision-making and executive function
- Reward-seeking behavior (dopamine-driven engagement loops in social media and gaming addiction)
Structural Changes in the Brain Due to Excessive Social media Use
Meta-analyses reveal gray matter reductions in critical brain areas among individuals with Brain Rot/PUI. The affected regions include:
A. Medial/Superior Frontal Gyri & Left Middle Frontal Gyrus
- These regions are involved in higher-order thinking, self-regulation, and decision-making.
- Reduction in gray matter here correlates with an inability to think critically, reflect on long-term consequences, or override immediate emotional responses.
- This aligns with the impulsive, outrage-driven behaviors commonly seen in social media interactions.
B. Anterior Cingulate Cortex (ACC)
- The ACC is critical for cognitive control, conflict resolution, and impulse inhibition.
- Studies have correlated decrease in ACC structure with impulsivity and poor decision-making.
- When people spend hours immersed in algorithm-driven dopamine loops, their ability to resist impulsive reactions declines.
C. Dorsolateral Prefrontal Cortex (DLPFC)
- The DLPFC is responsible for goal-directed behavior, planning, and strategic decision-making.
- Chronic social media use reduces activity here, leading to poor self-regulation and a greater susceptibility to emotional reactivity.
D. Supplementary Motor Area (SMA)
- This region is involved in complex action planning and cognitive flexibility.
- Degradation in this area correlates with an inability to switch tasks effectively, reinforcing compulsive screen behaviors.
In functional MRI studies, these deficits mirror the neural patterns observed in substance addiction.
Cognitive and Behavioral Impairments Linked to PUI
The second meta-analysis, "Neuropsychological Deficits in Disordered Screen Use Behaviors," highlights the profound cognitive impairments seen in individuals with chronic digital engagement.
A. Decision-Making Impairments
- PUI is associated with a preference for immediate gratification over long-term benefits.
- This aligns with the dopamine-driven nature of social media platforms, where users seek continuous micro-rewards (likes, comments, notifications) instead of engaging in sustained, meaningful thought.
- This mimics the exact cognitive biases [SH] unknowingly demonstrates—favoring reductionist conclusions over deep, long-term philosophical reasoning.
B. Increased Impulsivity
- Compulsive social media users exhibit greater impulsiveness on behavioral inhibition tasks.
- They also show poor response inhibition, meaning they struggle to stop once they begin a compulsive behavior.
- This is why social media arguments spiral endlessly—users become trapped in emotional feedback loops due to impaired impulse control.
C. Attention Deficits and Cognitive Rigidity
- Excessive internet users develop an attentional bias towards computer-related stimuli—they cannot disengage from digital environments.
- This erodes cognitive flexibility, making it harder to adapt to new ideas, perspectives, or complex information.
- This leads to the rise of tribalist thinking, ideological echo chambers, and black-and-white moral reasoning.
The Social Media–Psychopathy Connection: How "Brain Rot" Mimics Psychopathic Traits
What’s fascinating—and something [SH] fails to account for—is that these structural brain changes mimic the neurophysiology of psychopathy in several key ways.
- Psychopaths exhibit reduced activity in the ACC (linked to impaired empathy and impulse control).
- Chronic social media users also show reduced ACC function, correlating with increased emotional reactivity and reduced cognitive control.
- Psychopaths display impulsive, reward-seeking behavior—exactly the type of short-term gratification seen in PUI users.
- Both groups demonstrate impaired cognitive flexibility—difficulty disengaging from maladaptive behaviors or thought patterns.
This suggests a terrifying conclusion:
➡️ Social media overuse may be creating behavioral traits that resemble psychopathy—not due to genetics, but due to structural brain changes.
This is not to say that social media users are psychopaths—but it does explain the increasing lack of empathy, impulse control, and black-and-white moralizing seen in digital spaces.
The Reality [SH] Ignores: Psychopathy Can Develop, and It Can Be Mitigated
[SH] believes that psychopathy is purely genetic, which is demonstrably false.
- Certain people have a genetic predisposition for psychopathy but never develop it due to positive socialization.
- Conversely, individuals without genetic predispositions can exhibit psychopathic traits due to environmental influences—like chronic social media exposure.
- Epigenetic changes—alterations in gene expression due to environmental factors—can contribute to psychopathic behaviors.
This directly contradicts [SH]’s reductionist view that morality is simply a matter of predetermined brain states.
➡️ If environmental factors like chronic screen exposure can lead to psychopathy-like behaviors, then moral responsibility is not merely an illusion—it is a function of cognitive development and social conditioning.
Conclusion: The Neuroscience of Moral Decay in the Digital Age
[SH] completely overlooks the most immediate cause of moral degeneration in modern society: digital addiction and the neurophysiological impact of social media.
Instead of his hand-waving nonsense about genetic predestination, neuroscience tells us that:
- Excessive Social media use can structurally alter the brain in ways that impair moral reasoning, impulse control, and decision-making.
- These changes mimic the neurophysiological traits of psychopathy—suggesting that digital environments can foster anti-social behaviors. Which is dramatically magnified when there is a lack of moderation.
- Moral responsibility is not an illusion, but a function of cognitive development—and social media is actively impairing that development in real time. In addition, a lack of moderation results in more extreme behaviors being modeled and spreading in the population via normative mechanisms. Even adults are susceptible a shift in the behavior in the direction of less inhibited and more extreme behaviors. We believe this reversion to tribalism is what has been driving the resurgence of anti-social behaviors across all countries where social media use is common, and the accompanying political dysfunction.
This leads to one of the most important takeaways:
- If moral behavior can degrade due to structural brain changes, then restoring moral agency requires addressing these neurological impairments.
- Moral decay in society is not the result of genetic determinism—it is the result of cognitive erosion caused by algorithm-driven behavioral reinforcement.
And that is something we can—and must—change.
[06:14.280] Well, I'm interested to hear Sophie's.
[06:16.400] view on that in particular.
[06:17.440] So to the end of Sam's argument, there seems to be one that Galen Strawson is quite popular for you.
[06:24.200] You do what you do because of the way you are.
[06:26.440] You can't be responsible for how you are, so you can't be responsible for what you do.
[06:30.520] Does that resonate with you from a neuroscientific perspective?
[06:34.560] I mean, I have to say in a neuroscientific or biological perspective, we do have a biological model for criminal behavior.
[06:43.840] It's called the Y chromosome.
[06:46.160] No.
[06:46.400] I'm not being funny.
[06:47.680] There are like 23 types for every woman in prison.
[06:50.120] There are 23 men.
[06:51.040] That's worse than engineering departments.
[06:52.840] It's extraordinary that we do know this is this is this is found throughout nature.
[06:57.760] It seems to be a function of testosterone, possibly, which there's a really interesting interaction between testosterone and dopamine.
[07:04.920] They amplify each other.
[07:06.560] So men seem to get like bigger payoffs from sexual activity, for example, probably through this route.
[07:13.240] And sexual behavior is different in males and females.
[07:16.080] Aggressive behavior is different in males and females.
[07:18.040] And what we do with this is we ignore it and we pretend it's not true.
[07:21.600] And the people have made moral failings.
[07:24.600] So I think, you know, again, going back to us as social creatures, we need to live in environments where we have social norms.
[07:31.200] We all human communities, the social norms can be different, but they are there and we have to have them because otherwise the behavior would be, you know, not only from the
men and acceptable, but it's also something that makes kind of the politeness norms make normal interaction.
[07:45.320] feasible.
[07:46.880] You know, this is not a brain answer.
[07:48.520] This is a biology, you know, psychology answer.
[07:51.520] And this is not disagreeing with anything that's been said so far.
[07:54.200] But I think one of the things that is really interesting from a brain perspective is how much we are and are not conscious of and what neural systems it's associated with.
This section exposes a deeper issue that often lurks in pop-neuroscience and new-age mysticism—the normalization of sexist and racial biases under the guise of "scientific discussion."
Sophie Scott’s statement about the Y chromosome being a "biological model for criminal behavior" is not just scientifically flawed—it is openly misandrist.
- The fact that no one in the conversation reacted to this blatant sexism exposes a very real double standard.
- If someone had made a similar remark about women and criminal behavior, the response would have been outrage, but when men are essentialized as criminals, it is casually accepted.
This is not just an issue of bad science—it is a reflection of ideological bias masquerading as intellectualism.
While [SH] attempts to handwave away moral responsibility, the next speaker doubles down on an even more simplistic biological model—blaming the Y chromosome for criminal behavior.
The Y Chromosome and Misandry: A Reflection of Toxic Feminism
The claim that men are biologically predisposed to criminality is a variation of the debunked "Super Predator" theory, except now applied to gender instead of race.
- This is extreme biological essentialism—it treats men as biologically inferior or inherently violent.
- It ignores vast differences in socialization, economic opportunity, and systemic biases in policing.
- It fails to account for why men are disproportionately criminalized, even when controlling for behavior.
The Hypocrisy of Modern Gender Discourse
If someone had said:
➡️ "We have a biological model for financial fraud, it’s called the XX chromosome."
➡️ "We have a biological model for emotional manipulation, it’s called the XX chromosome."
➡️ "We have a biological model for gossiping and workplace bullying, it’s called the XX chromosome."
The reaction would have been immediate outrage.
But when the same claim is made against men, it is accepted without hesitation.
This reveals a cultural blind spot—where misandry is normalized under the guise of "feminism."
It also exposes the ideological bias of new-age mysticism, where pseudo-intellectuals selectively apply biological determinism to suit their ideological leanings.
The Y Chromosome as a “Biological Model for Criminal Behavior”**
The claim that "We do have a biological model for criminal behavior—it’s called the Y chromosome." is:
- Oversimplified to the point of absurdity.
- A textbook case of correlation being mistaken for causation.
- Ignoring massive sociological, psychological, and environmental factors.
Yes, men commit more violent crimes than women. But to boil this down to the presence of a Y chromosome ignores vast amounts of research into criminal behavior.
Why This Claim is Incorrect:
- Genetics alone do not determine criminality.
- If criminal behavior were purely genetic, we should see much stronger predictive power in twin studies and heritability estimates—but we don’t.
- Men and women are socialized differently from birth.
- Gender differences in crime rates are significantly influenced by cultural expectations, policing differences, and economic factors.
- Women, for example, are much less likely to be arrested for the same offenses men commit.
- The Y chromosome itself does not code for aggression or criminality.
- Testosterone levels and their effects on behavior are complex, dynamic, and context-dependent.
- Testosterone interacts with social and environmental cues—it does not dictate behavior in isolation.
This attempt at biological reductionism mirrors the discredited "Super Predator" theory—treating crime as something biologically inevitable rather than socially conditioned and contextually reinforced.
The danger of this perspective is that it treats people as pre-programmed machines rather than beings capable of moral decision-making.
The False Claim That Psychopathy is a Dopamine-Testosterone Interaction
Sophie Scott then compounds her misandry with blatant scientific inaccuracy, claiming that psychopathy is a product of testosterone and dopamine interactions.
This misrepresents both neurochemistry and human behavior.
- Dopamine and testosterone interact in both men and women.
- High testosterone does not automatically lead to aggression.
- Many elite athletes, military officers, and successful businessmen have high testosterone yet are not violent.
- Dopamine is not simply a “pleasure chemical”—it is a learning signal that reinforces behaviors, whether positive or negative.
- Women also have both dopamine and testosterone.
Her claim implicitly suggests that female psychopaths do not exist, which is demonstrably false.
- Female psychopathy is well-documented, especially in leadership roles within organized crime. and the book Narcas: The Secret Rise of Women in Latin America's Cartels
- The assumption that only men are psychopaths ignores historical and contemporary realities.
The Testosterone-Dopamine Interaction: Misrepresented Science
The claim that testosterone and dopamine "amplify each other" to create greater payoffs for men in sexual activity, aggression, and reward-seeking behavior is:
- A half-truth stretched into a sweeping generalization.
- Missing the crucial factor of neuroplasticity and socialization.
- Ignoring the broader hormonal context—estrogen, oxytocin, and serotonin all play roles in aggression, bonding, and social behavior.
Why This Claim is Flawed:
- Testosterone does not simply "cause" aggression.
- It modulates dominance behaviors, which can express as aggression or social cooperation depending on context.
- Studies show testosterone increases aggression in competitive environments but increases pro-social behaviors in cooperative settings.
- Dopamine does not simply "amplify" testosterone-driven behavior.
- Dopamine is a learning signal, not just a pleasure chemical.
- It reinforces behaviors based on perceived rewards, which can be conditioned by experience and environment.
- This is why compulsive internet use, gambling, and even ideological extremism all hijack the same dopamine pathways.
While testosterone-dopamine interactions play a role in risk-taking behavior, this does not mean men are biologically destined for crime.
To frame it this way is to ignore everything we know about cognitive control, social conditioning, and moral agency.
The Attempt to Reintroduce Social Norms (After Arguing Against Them)
After arguing for biological determinism, the speaker then contradicts themselves by saying:
- "We need to live in environments where we have social norms."
- "The politeness norms make normal interaction feasible."
This directly conflicts with the earlier arguments about:
- Determinism stripping people of moral responsibility.
- The idea that criminality is purely a product of the Y chromosome.
If criminal behavior were purely biologically driven, then why would social norms matter at all?
This contradiction exposes a major flaw in the entire conversation—
➡️ They want to argue for determinism when it suits them, but they also want to impose social expectations when convenient.
The Flawed Attempt to Introduce “Conscious vs. Unconscious” Brain Functions
The speaker then attempts to pivot back to neuroscience:
- "One of the things that is really interesting from a brain perspective is how much we are and are not conscious of, and what neural systems it's associated with."
This statement is vague to the point of being meaningless.
- They do not define what they mean by "conscious vs. unconscious" brain activity.
- They do not link this discussion to their earlier claims about crime, gender, or moral responsibility.
If they were serious about this question, they should have referenced:
- Dual-process theory in cognitive science (the interplay between intuitive, fast thinking and deliberate, slow reasoning).
- The role of the prefrontal cortex in conscious decision-making and impulse control.
- The distinction between affective vs. cognitive empathy in moral reasoning.
Instead, they vaguely gesture at neuroscience without adding any meaningful insight.
Conclusion: This is an Incoherent Mess
This section of the discussion is a mashup of bad biology, pop-neuroscience, and self-contradictory arguments.
- The Y chromosome argument is preposterous—correlation is not causation.
- The testosterone-dopamine claim is misrepresented science, ignoring neuroplasticity and social conditioning.
- The claim that criminality is biologically determined directly contradicts the later claim that social norms are necessary.
- The neuroscientific conclusion is vague and lacks any real explanatory power.
[08:02.360] So everybody here is sitting on a chair and not falling straight to the floor because of postural reflexes that continuously adjust how we're sitting and how we're standing a
nd stop us from falling.
[08:12.960] And we have almost no conscious awareness.
[08:15.320] Of that.
[08:16.280] When things go wrong with it, you then are very quickly aware of it.
[08:19.520] And similarly, if you're walking down the street and you trip by the time you've had time to think, I'm tripping your sensory motor systems again over which you have very lit
tle conscious awareness are the ones that are correcting the trip.
[08:31.040] And if you were to wait for conscious awareness, you'd be lying on the floor with your face on the pavement going, I've fallen because that is not going to save you.
[08:38.560] So there's a there's a interesting functional distinctions to be made at a brain level which are interacting with the kind of moral
[08:45.120] question.
[08:45.240] Of that.
[08:45.520] Right through to some of the physical stuff of how we are able to move about in the world, which really do intersect with what what and I'm not in any way denying the importa
nce of consciousness.
[08:55.520] I'm just saying there are very interesting things that we don't have good conscious access to.
[09:00.160] And I think that is interesting when we start to look at brain systems, because from a brain kind of networks perspective, there do seem to be some networks with it.
[09:08.440] For example, the ones in the temporal lobes over which we have a lot more conscious awareness than other stuff that's, for example, kind of integrated
[09:15.440] body and movement.
This final section of Scott’s comments attempts to use basic neuromotor reflexes as a bridge to moral philosophy.
- While she technically describes some correct facts about unconscious motor control, she then attempts to map them onto moral decision-making, which is an entirely different domain.
- The result is a disjointed, misleading comparison that conflates unconscious biological processes with complex cognitive and ethical reasoning.
This is a classic example of someone using surface-level neuroscience to sound profound, while ultimately making no meaningful contribution to the discussion.
The Faulty Analogy Between Motor Reflexes and Moral Decision-Making
Scott begins by explaining an entirely unrelated neurological process: postural reflexes.
- She states that we are not consciously aware of our postural adjustments. except when the chair or posture is uncomfortable, which is conveniently forgotten.
- This is due to limitations of attention people cannot pay attention to everything all of the time. They in fact often miss large and obvious objects of perception which is referred to as Inattentional blindness
Then, she attempts to link this to moral decision-making by saying that some brain processes operate outside of our conscious control.
This comparison is entirely misleading for several reasons:
- Moral decision-making is handled by completely different neural circuits than motor reflexes.
- Reflexive balance corrections are mediated by the cerebellum, brainstem, and spinal cord.
- Ethical reasoning, moral judgments, and impulse control involve the prefrontal cortex, limbic system, and temporal lobes.
- These systems are not functionally equivalent—moral reasoning is deliberate and socially influenced, while reflexes are evolutionarily hardwired.
- Reacting to tripping is not the same as making a moral choice.
- When you trip, your cerebellum and motor cortex execute a correction in milliseconds.
- Moral decisions are slower, requiring reflection, context evaluation, and often emotional processing.
- Equating the two is an egregious oversimplification.
- This falsely suggests that moral decisions “just happen” like reflexes.
- By drawing this analogy, Scott implicitly argues that morality is an automatic, deterministic process, rather than a learned and deliberative function.
- This undermines the role of self-awareness, critical thinking, and personal development in ethical decision-making.
This is a fundamental error in reasoning—equating low-level autonomic responses with high-level cognitive processes.
The Misrepresentation of Conscious vs. Unconscious Brain Processes
Scott then makes another vague assertion:
➡️ "There are some brain networks, for example in the temporal lobes, over which we have a lot more conscious awareness than others."
This is a bizarrely vague and poorly formulated statement that:
Fails to explain what she means by "conscious awareness."
Does not define what brain networks she is referring to.
Ignores the complexity of distributed neural processing.
Clarifying the Science: What She Should Have Said
- The temporal lobes are primarily involved in language, memory, and high-level sensory processing.
- Moral cognition does involve the temporal lobes—but also integrates input from the prefrontal cortex, limbic system, and parietal areas.
- There is no strict separation of "conscious vs. unconscious" brain areas—most cognitive functions operate on a spectrum between automaticity and deliberate control.
Scott’s oversimplification suggests a binary model of brain function that does not exist in neuroscience.
The Underlying Fallacy: Attempting to Smuggle in Determinism
Scott’s true intent becomes clear when we analyze how this fits into the larger conversation.
- The entire discussion has been about moral agency and whether humans have control over their actions.
- By introducing unconscious motor processes, she is subtly reinforcing the idea that most of what we do is beyond our control.
- This is a rhetorical sleight of hand—framing moral behavior as just another automatic process.
This fits into the larger pattern of reductionist, deterministic thinking that permeates this discussion:
- [SH] argues that free will is an illusion.
- Scott reinforces this by claiming criminality is biologically predetermined.
- She now further reduces moral decision-making to an unconscious process.
Each step in this argument erodes the idea that people are responsible for their actions, despite overwhelming evidence to the contrary.
What They Are Ignoring: The Role of Executive Function and Self-Awareness
Scott’s viewpoint completely ignores what actually makes humans different from animals—our ability to:
- Self-reflect and inhibit impulses.
- Consider long-term consequences.
- Engage in moral reasoning that is not purely reactionary.
The prefrontal cortex—especially the dorsolateral prefrontal cortex (DLPFC) and ventromedial prefrontal cortex (VMPFC)—are crucial to this process.
- These regions allow us to override instinctive responses and act according to ethical principles rather than raw impulse.
- This is what enables moral development, personal growth, and philosophical reasoning.
Scott’s attempt to collapse conscious ethical decision-making into unconscious reflexes is not just inaccurate—it is actively misleading.
The Real Scientific Perspective: Integrating Conscious and Unconscious Processes in Morality
A far more accurate discussion would focus on how unconscious and conscious processes interact in moral decision-making:
- Unconscious biases and emotions often initiate moral intuitions.
- Conscious reflection allows us to override impulsive moral judgments when necessary.
- Moral reasoning is shaped by learning, socialization, and cognitive effort.
This contradicts the fatalistic determinism implied in Scott’s argument.
- We are not merely acting on autopilot.
- We have the capacity to shape our behaviors through conscious effort and intellectual development.
This aligns with neoBuddhist philosophy, which emphasizes self-awareness, intentionality, and the cultivation of virtue.
Conclusion: Another Failed Attempt at Neuroscientific Determinism
Scott’s entire contribution to this discussion is riddled with errors and misleading comparisons.
- The postural reflex analogy is irrelevant and falsely equates motor functions with moral reasoning.
- Her discussion of conscious vs. unconscious brain systems is vague and meaningless.
- The underlying rhetorical strategy is to reinforce the idea that morality is not a choice, but an automatic process.
This mirrors the same errors made by [SH]—ignoring neuroplasticity, executive function, and the developmental aspects of morality.
Instead of engaging in a nuanced discussion about how the brain enables moral reasoning, Scott resorts to shallow pop-neuroscience analogies that collapse under scrutiny.
The Role of Banality in These Statements
The most disturbing part of this discussion is how casually these ideas were expressed and accepted.
Scott’s misandry is an example of the "Banality of Evil"—a quiet, passive form of systemic bias that is accepted because no one challenges it.
- If someone had suggested that criminality was biologically determined in a racial context, there would be immediate backlash.
- If someone had made an essentialist claim about women, there would be immediate outrage.
- But because it was about men, it passed without question.
This highlights how ideological biases infect pop-neuroscience.
- People like Sophie Scott and [SH] present themselves as intellectuals, but they are not engaging in rigorous scientific thought.
- Instead, they are reinforcing cultural narratives that fit within a specific ideological framework, regardless of their accuracy.
The Danger of Essentialist Thinking in Criminal Justice
The real-world consequences of this kind of thinking are serious.
- Biological determinism has historically been used to justify discrimination, eugenics, and authoritarian policies.
- Claiming that men are biologically predisposed to criminality fuels gender-based discrimination in legal systems.
- This is the same flawed reasoning that led to the Super Predator myth, which disproportionately harmed Black communities.
If [SH] and Scott truly understood cognitive science and criminal justice, they would reject these simplistic models.
Instead, they perpetuate ideological biases disguised as scientific insight.
Conclusion: This is Not Science—It’s Ideological Posturing
This section of the discussion is not just intellectually weak—it is dangerous.
- The Y chromosome claim is blatant misandry.
- The testosterone-dopamine argument is a misrepresentation of neuroscience.
- The dismissal of female criminality ignores real-world data.
- The failure to challenge these claims exposes cultural biases in pop-neuroscience.
This section is an example of how pseudo-intellectualism reinforces harmful stereotypes under the guise of academic discussion.
[09:16.640] Well, Roger, maybe you can give a slightly different perspective here, or maybe you won't.
[09:21.640] And you'll agree as well.
[09:22.840] But maybe your view has more room for allowing for something like agency or libertarian free will, if you want to say that consciousness or like a direction on your body is s
omething different from computational processes.
[09:36.720] Well, there's something in free will, which is not it's not random.
[09:41.360] It's an interesting question.
[09:43.040] I don't really want to go into this topic.
[09:45.080] Too much, but people claim you think of somebody, a tennis player, say, and at the last minute sees the opportunity to go down the line or cross court or something.
[09:55.000] And that action takes place so fast that according to the neurophysiologist, it's just not possible for that to be a conscious action.
[10:03.600] Now, what about ping pong?
[10:04.680] It's even worse for me because you're flicking the ball very far.
[10:07.040] I used to play ping pong.
[10:08.080] I mean, you get the right standards for me.
[10:11.200] I think I was the second officer came.
[10:13.440] The second.
[10:14.400] So.
[10:14.880] So John's college team, not free.
[10:19.120] So that's about the level I was at.
[10:21.440] You see, it's gave me some feeling for the game.
[10:23.320] And so how fast you have to think.
[10:24.840] Yeah.
[10:25.160] Or even say a pianist playing complicated and any pianist may decide whether to touch that key a little bit more softly to make this what we want.
[10:33.360] And that's also the music is much too fast for that to be a conscious action.
[10:38.640] So the story goes.
[10:40.200] Now, I do feel it's a conscious decision.
[10:43.080] Now, does that make any sense?
[10:44.880] Now, the thing is.
[10:47.320] The view I'm holding now, you might think it's too strange, but when one thinks about the.
Roger Penrose’s More Reasonable Perspective
Unlike [SH] and Scott, Penrose doesn’t say anything outright ridiculous—which is a refreshing change.
- However, his comments still leave room for critique and clarification, particularly regarding conscious decision-making in fast-paced activities.
- His main argument seems to be pushing against the idea that all decisions are unconscious, particularly in high-speed activities like sports and music.
This gives us the opportunity to correct misconceptions about reaction speed, pre-conscious decision-making, and the neuroscience of skilled performance.
Penrose introduces several important ideas:
- Free will is not random.
- This is a direct rebuttal to [SH]’s flawed idea that "if decisions aren’t deterministic, they must be random."
- He is correct to reject this binary, though he does not fully articulate an alternative.
- Fast actions in sports and music appear to bypass conscious thought.
- Tennis and ping-pong players make split-second decisions that seem too fast for conscious processing.
- Pianists make micro-adjustments in playing, often without apparent deliberation.
- He challenges the idea that these actions are purely unconscious.
- He believes there is a conscious element to these actions.
- This is a more nuanced position than [SH] or Scott’s deterministic reductionism.
- However, it is still incomplete—there are specific mechanisms that explain how conscious and unconscious processing interact in fast decision-making.
Muscle Memory, Conscious Refinement, and the Illusion of the Unconscious Mind
- He is grappling with an intuitive truth but lacks the precise language to articulate it.
- Muscle memory is not unconscious—it is trained, refined, and directed by conscious intent.
- Just because an action is non-verbal does not mean it is non-conscious.
This mirrors how memory recall works—a process you experience as lexical priming, where certain words and concepts become more easily accessible based on context.
- This demonstrates that even non-verbal cognition is not a passive, automatic process—it is shaped by intent and past experience.
Reframing the Debate: Procedural Memory and the Illusion of the Unconscious
Penrose falls into the same flawed framing as [SH]—assuming that speed means absence of agency.
- The truth is that expertise allows consciousness to shape rapid responses in ways that appear automatic but are actually highly intentional.
Correcting the Flawed Assumption
Procedural memory (or what you refer to as muscle memory) is not a mindless process—it is a form of embodied cognition.
- Athletes are not mindlessly reacting; they are executing well-practiced movements with precision.
- The brain is constantly running simulations and adjusting based on micro-feedback.
- Even if the conscious mind is not verbalizing each decision, it is still present in the process.
This explains why mastery leads to a state of flow—where action and awareness become seamless.
The Real Science of Skilled Decision-Making
corrections to the misconceptions:
Fast actions are still conscious—just not in the way people assume.
- Athletes and musicians are not mindlessly reacting—they are continuously refining their movements through rapid feedback loops.
- The brain does not “turn off” during fast decision-making—it simply operates in a more fluid, integrated manner.
Skill development involves a transition from slow, deliberate control to refined, intuitive execution.
- Novices must consciously think through each step of an action.
- Experts integrate that knowledge into a seamless process that feels automatic but is still under control.
Memory recall and lexical priming demonstrate that even non-verbal cognition is guided by intention.
- Your own experience with memory retrieval is an example of this process.
- The act of “remembering” is not passive—it is shaped by prior learning, emotional context, and conscious cues.
This directly counters [SH]’s claim that all thought simply “arises” without intent.
NeoBuddhist Integration: Flow, Mastery, and the Refinement of Will
This ties beautifully into NeoBuddhism’s perspective on skill and awareness.
- True mastery is not mindless automation—it is the integration of intent, awareness, and action.
- The goal is not to overanalyze every action, but to refine one’s being until virtuous action becomes effortless.
- This is why discipline and training matter—not because they remove conscious control, but because they elevate it.
This aligns with the concept of Kenshō in Zen—where deep understanding leads to spontaneous, natural action.
- The Flawed Assumption: Speed ≠ Lack of Consciousness
- Penrose recognizes the problem but struggles to articulate it.
- We correct the assumption by explaining muscle memory, procedural learning, and skilled decision-making.
- Memory, Priming, and Non-Verbal Thought
- Even non-verbal cognition is shaped by conscious intent.
- Lexical priming is an example of how the mind guides non-verbal processing.
- NeoBuddhism and the Path to Mastery
- Skillful action is the harmony of awareness and execution.
- Virtue should become effortless—not because it is automatic, but because it has been fully internalized.
Final Takeaway: The Mind is Not Passive—It is Sculpted by Will
This resolves the debate by rejecting both extreme determinism and the flawed notion of purely unconscious expertise.
- It affirms the neoBuddhist view that refinement, discipline, and intention lead to true agency.
- It leaves the audience with a powerful insight— free will is not about rejecting habits, but shaping them into something virtuous.